India’s Elite Undergraduate Institutions are Hurting It (Published on Youth Ki Awaaz)

another brick in the wallIndia’s elite undergraduate institutions are hurting it by having admission processes which cause a systemic suppression of innovation, leadership and thoughtfulness in a majority of the high schools in the country. One of the first things you read in any introductory economics text book is         that people respond to incentives. The curriculum of a bulk of the high schools in           Another Brick in the Wall – Pink Floyd             any country is typically designed to help                                                                                         students secure admission to the most       sought undergraduate institutions in the country.

(This article was published on Youth Ki Awaaz. Link: How India’s Elite Undergraduate Institutions Are Suppressing Innovation and Leadership)

Continue reading

Barbarians at the Gate: Leveraged Buyouts

Barbarians at the gate

I watched the movie Barbarians at the Gate (1993) yesterday and was interested in understanding one of its central themes, the concept of leverage buyouts (LBOs).

The movie is based on a book written by the investigative journalists Bryan Burrough and John Helyar about the leveraged buyout of RJR Nabisco, a company that primarily sold tobacco and food products. The book in turn was essentially a compilation of a series of articles that the authors wrote for the Wall Street Journal.

The leveraged buyout of RJR Nabisco in 1988 was carried out in an environment that was critical of corporate and    executive excesses. There was a bidding war for the buyout of the company.

Continue reading

Kierkegaard’s Skepticism of Hegelian Philosophy

hegel statue

 

In one of the first sections of “Fear and Trembling”, Kierkegaard (as his pseudonymous self, Johannes de Silentio) notes,

“ I for my part have devoted a good deal of time to the understanding of the Hegelian philosophy, I believe also that I understand it tolerably well, but when in spite of the trouble I have taken there are certain passages I cannot understand, I am foolhardy enough to think that he himself has not been quite clear.”

Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel                                                                                                            (1770 – 1831)

Observe that he sets the tone for opposing Hegelian philosophy over the course of his discussion very early in this work. So it is imperative for one to understand the main themes in Hegelian philosophy in order to fully appreciate Kierkegaard’s discussion about “the second inwardness” in the later sections of “Fear and Trembling”.

Continue reading

Jean Paul Sartre: The Concept of Bad Faith and its Role in Ethical Analysis

bad_faithBad faith (mauvais foi) is essentially inauthenticity for Jean Paul Sartre. He thinks of bad faith as an attempt to evade the responsibility of discovering and understanding one’s authentic self. Bad faith is thereby an attempt to escape the freedom that Sartre believes is an inherent feature of our lives.  When Sartre says, “Consciousness is what it is not and is not what it is,” he means that consciousness is something that is a constantly integrated combination of facticity and transcendence which                                                                        can be taken to mean the past and future                                                                                      respectively.

In the section discussing the patterns of bad faith in Being and Nothing, Sartre notes that, “The basic concept which is thus engendered, utilizes the double property of the human being, who is at once a facticity and a transcendence, These two aspects of human reality are and ought to be capable of a valid coordination. But bad faith does not wish either to coordinate them nor to surmount them in a synthesis.” It is thereby imperative to understand these two dimensions of human consciousness to understand bad faith.

Continue reading

Jean Paul Sartre: Nothingness and Human Freedom

OLYMPUS DIGITAL CAMERAIn order to understand the relation between Sartre’s understanding of Nothingness (the nihilation of being) and his understanding of human freedom, one must analyze the duality of the Being-for-itself and the Being-in-itself that is at the core of Sartre’s analogy. Sartre notes that human consciousness is always conscious of something else. However human consciousness itself is really nothingness. So without something to be conscious of, our consciousness cannot exist as it defines itself with respect to the things which it is conscious of. So he essentially asserts that consciousness itself is                               Jean Paul Sartre (1905 – 1980)                  nothingness and that the things which the                                                                                    consciousness is conscious of has some form                                                                                of being.

He explores the paradoxical notion of consciousness being self-aware as one might wonder how one can one be aware of a consciousness that is nothing. Sartre introduces the notion of a pre-reflective cogito (built from the cogito of Rene Descartes) to explain this paradox.

Continue reading

“God is Dead” – Friedrich Nietzche

The Gay Science: Book III  – Aphorism 125 (link)

Nietzsche187a

When the mad man rushes into the market place with a lantern and declares that he seeks God, the men around him mock him and indicate that they don’t believe in God. The mad man then declares that God was killed by all of them.

It is important to point out that stating “God is dead” is a tacit admission that God once existed. What Nietzche is indicating is that we created God to fill up our spiritual voids at one point in time, but we no longer need God and hence we have killed him. It should be highlighted that Nietzche is implying that God is a human conception whose functionality has run out. He goes onto highlight that this lack of reliance on God would be (Friedrich Nietzche 1844 – 1900)        chaotic.

The men around him who don’t believe in God eventually greet his outburst with silence. One must understand that Nietzche is trying to indicate that we might have stopped believing in God (or given up our faith in a religion), but we have only replaced this faith in God, with faith in other forms of “truths.” He is indicating that the new systems of scientific positivism, democracy, feminism, utilitarianism and so on, have simply taken the place of the truths that were once represented by God. This is the reason why the men around him greet him with him laughter, followed by an astonished silence.

Continue reading

Friedrich Nietzche’s Analysis of the Master Morality and Slave Morality

master moralityNietzche’s general project in the “The Genealogy of Morals” is to provide a historical account of morality. He doesn’t explicitly aim to offer any prescriptions, but rather chooses to provide his account on the manner in which we have come to arrive at morality as it is today.

There are two principle kinds of morality that Nietzche analyzes in the first essay of The Genealogy of Morals. They are the master morality and slave                                                                         morality.

For Nietzche, the master morality is represented by the values of the individuals who actually exert (what he believes to be) human being’s inherent will to power. In this form of morality, the individuals first establish themselves as good, and then establish that the people who aren’t like them as bad, as an afterthought. He notes that the Greeks referred to their servants and slaves in a fashion that radiated their obvious belief that their slaves were insignificant creatures.

Continue reading

Analyzing Dostoevsky’s Underground Man based on Kierkegaard’s Discussion of Despair

dostoevskyIn the Sickness Unto Death, Kierkegaard explains that man is “a synthesis of the finite and the infinite, of the temporal and the eternal, of freedom and necessity.” The components of these two parameters (the finite and the infinite) need to be in a sort of equilibrium through repeated self-reflection “grounded” in the reliance on God to abolish despair. He says that there are two forms of despair: the despair of not willing be one’s          Fyodor Dostoyevsky (1821 – 1881)                   own self and the despair of willing to be                                                                                          one’s own self.

As he explains, the despair of willing to be one’s own self, Kierkegaard uses the example of an individual suffering from vertigo to show that refusing to recognize one’s reliance on the “Power” (or God) through repeated self-reflection causes the self to be out of balance, which in turn leads to despair. So he believes that willing to be one’s own self without relating to the intrinsic God in us through defiance results in further despair. In his words, if “by himself and by himself only he would abolish the despair, then by all the labour he expends, he is only laboring himself into a deeper despair.”

Continue reading

Soren Kierkegaard’s Knights of Infinite Resignation, Knights of Faith and Tragic Heroes

soren kierkegaardIn Fear and Trembling, Kierkegaard explains the nature of the knights of infinite resignation through the use of an example of a young man who falls in love with a princess he can never get in “reality.”

The knights of infinite resignation allow every fiber of their being to be filled with love for the princess as this love is their sole purpose in life. These knights recognize that everything is possible in the spiritual world but that everything is not possible in the finite world. They make the impossible, possible through a spiritual expression. This spiritual expression is renouncing the impossible in the finite world. So in Kierkegaard’s analogy, the young man renounces his love for the princess in the finite world and allows the pain caused by his unsatisfied desire to                                                                                                  reconcile him spiritually.

Continue reading

A Note on the “Others” in Heidegger’s philosophy

Martin_Heidegger
In order to understand the role of “the Others” in Heidegger’s philosophy, one must first develop an understanding of “Dasein”. Heidegger essentially distinguishes Dasein from the notion of a Cartesian mind which is a sort of an isolated and immaterial being. The word Dasein by itself means existence in the German language, however Heidegger dexterously crafts a technical interpretation of the word to express one of his                              Martin Heidegger (1889 – 1976)                    quintessential philosophical insights.

The word “sein” means “to be”. The prefix “Da” means “there”. So “Dasein” means “being out there”. More explicitly Dasein is supposed to be an understanding of a human being as being out there in the world, interacting with a familiar environment (such as the totality of equipment that are references to one other which are understood in terms of their use), and other beings, with a particular set of moods. Heidegger asserts that every consciousness out in the world is constantly orienting itself to situations. These situations cause one’s consciousness to be directed. Note that all acts of consciousness have meaning in virtue of the objects to which these acts are directed. Now the being of Dasein in the world is nothing like the being of some inanimate object. For instance a pen on a desk can never touch the desk or the air around it because it lacks a consciousness that will allow it to interpret other entities or the world. It is merely “present-at-hand”. Only to the conscious being does the pen make sense as a member of the intricate interconnected web of references connecting a totality of such equipment (the pen, paper, desk and ink are understood in virtue of their references to each other).

Continue reading